\( \newcommand{\matr}[1] {\mathbf{#1}} \newcommand{\vertbar} {\rule[-1ex]{0.5pt}{2.5ex}} \newcommand{\horzbar} {\rule[.5ex]{2.5ex}{0.5pt}} \newcommand{\E} {\mathrm{E}} \)
deepdream of
          a sidewalk
Show Question
\( \newcommand{\cat}[1] {\mathrm{#1}} \newcommand{\catobj}[1] {\operatorname{Obj}(\mathrm{#1})} \newcommand{\cathom}[1] {\operatorname{Hom}_{\cat{#1}}} \newcommand{\multiBetaReduction}[0] {\twoheadrightarrow_{\beta}} \newcommand{\betaReduction}[0] {\rightarrow_{\beta}} \newcommand{\betaEq}[0] {=_{\beta}} \newcommand{\string}[1] {\texttt{"}\mathtt{#1}\texttt{"}} \newcommand{\symbolq}[1] {\texttt{`}\mathtt{#1}\texttt{'}} \newcommand{\groupMul}[1] { \cdot_{\small{#1}}} \newcommand{\groupAdd}[1] { +_{\small{#1}}} \newcommand{\inv}[1] {#1^{-1} } \newcommand{\bm}[1] { \boldsymbol{#1} } \require{physics} \require{ams} \require{mathtools} \)
Math and science::Algebra::Aluffi

Groups. Order.

There are two related concepts of order: the order of an element, and the order of a group.

Element order

Let \( g \) be an element of group \( G \). \( g \) is said to have finite order iff there exists a natural number \( n \) such that \( g^n = e \). We say that the order of \( g \) is \( k \) iff \( k \) is the smallest natural such that \( g^k = e \). We write \( |g| = k \).

If there is no such natural number, \( g \) does not have finite order and we write \( |g| = \infty \).

Notation: \( e \) is shorthand for \( e_G \), the identity element of group \( G \). \( g^n \) is notation for \( g \bullet g \bullet ... g \), \( g \) composed with itself \( n \) times.

Group order

Let \( G \) be a group. If \( G \) has finite elements, then we say that the order of \( G \) is the number of its elements. We write \( |G| \) to denote the order of \( G \). Otherwise, when \( G \) has infinite elements, we write \( |G| = \infty \).

4 Lemmas

For a group \( G \) and element \( g \), \( |g| \le |G| \).

Proof. This is vacuously true if \( |G| = \infty \). If \( G \) has finite order, then consider \( |G| + 1 \) powers of \( g \): \( g^0, g^1, g^2 ... g^{|G|} \). All of these powers can't be unique, otherwise \( G \) would have more than \( |G| \) elements. Let \( g^i = g^j \) be two repeated elements in the sequence (with \( i < j \)). Then \( g^{j-i} \) must be the identity, and we have \( |g| \le j - i \le |G| \).

Let \( g \) be an element of a group. If \( g^n = e \), then \( |g| \) is a divisor of \( n \).

Aluffi cheats a little in his proof. I think the proof requires an inductive proof. I think it would be worth checking out how the inductive proof is set up.

An immediate consequence of the above lemma is the following corollary:

Let \( g \) be an element with finite order, and let \( N \in \mathbb{R} \). Then:

\[ g^N = e \iff N \text{ is a multiple of } |g|.\]

Let \( G \) be a group and \( g \in G \) be an element of finite order. Then for any \( m > 0 \), \( g^m \) has finite order. Specifically, the order of \( g^m \) is related to the order of \( g \) as follows:

\[ |g^m| = \frac{\operatorname{lcm}(m, |g|)}{m} = \frac{|g|}{\operatorname{gcd}(m, |g|)}. \]


Source

p47